Subject: [evol-psych] Darwin & Hume's moral sense Date: Thu, 14 Feb 2002 08:30:04 -0600 From: "Larry Arnhart"To: In summarizing his account of the moral sense in the last chapter of THE DESCENT OF MAN, Darwin explains our experience of "ought" as expressing a certain kind of feeling: "Any instinct which is permanently stronger or more enduring than another, gives rise to a feeling which we express by saying that it ought to be obeyed." Although many philosophers today would say that this violates the is/ought dichotomy first stated by David Hume, I think that Darwin's biological theory of morality as rooted in moral feelings or sentiments was derived largely from his reading of Hume (as well as Adam Smith). Some of my reasoning is developed in my book, DARWINIAN NATURAL RIGHT: THE BIOLOGICAL ETHICS OF HUMAN NATURE (SUNY Press, 1998). The common interpretation of Hume as having separated "is" and "ought" depends on only one paragraph in his TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE. The textual context of this paragraph makes clear that Hume's claim is that moral distinctions are derived not from pure reason alone but from a moral sense. The historical context makes clear that Hume is restating Francis Hutcheson's criticisms of some early modern rationalists who believed that moral distinctions could be derived from abstract reasoning about structures in the universe that were completely independent of human nature. Far from denying that moral judgments are judgments of fact, Hume claims that they are factual judgments about the species-typical pattern of moral sentiments in specified circumstances. Hume compares moral judgments to judgments of secondary qualities such as colors. My judgment that this tomato is red is true if the object is so constituted as to induce the impression of red in normally sighted human beings viewing it under standard conditions. Similarly, my judgment that this person is morally praiseworthy is true if there person's conduct is such as to induce the sentiment of approbation in normal human beings under standard conditions. Just as an object can appear red to me when in fact it is not, so a person can appear praiseworthy to me when in fact he is not. The moral judgment whether some conduct would give to a normal spectator under standard conditions a moral sentiment of approbation is, Hume insists, "a plain matter of fact." The moral sentiment itself, however, is a feeling or passion rooted in human nature that cannot be produced by reason alone. Hume's comparison of moral judgments and judgments of color is apt. We know that although there is variation in color vocabulary across different languages, which reflects cultural variation, there is a regularity in those vocabularies that manifests the way the human visual system divides the spectrum of visible light into the principal colors blue, green, yellow, and red. This color spectrum is arbitrary in an ultimately biological sense, because different visual systems could have evolved. But once it evolved in the human species, it could not be radically altered by culture, although there can be some cultural variation in the details of color vocabulary. Similarly, there can be some variation in our moral vocabularies across cultures, but there will be a regularity in those moral vocabularies that reflects the regularity in the moral emotions of normal people. Of course, just as there are people born color-blind, so there might be people born as potential psychopaths who do not feel the moral emotions of normal people. The case of primary psychopaths actually reveals the fundamental importance of moral emotions. Psychopaths do not suffer from any deficit in their capacities for abstract reasoning, and yet they lack a moral sense because they do not feel the moral emotions of normal people. Edward Westermarck's account of incest avoidance shows that our moral emotions of aversion to incest manifest the same pattern of natural regularity and cultural variability that one sees in color vocabularies. We are naturally inclined to feel sexual aversion to those with whom we have been raised, and this aversion expresses itself in customary and legal rules of incest avoidance. Almost universally, we will feel strong emotions of aversion towards sex between full siblings or between parents and their children. Various lines of evidence suggest that this is an epigenetic rule favored by natural selection to avoid the deleterious effects of inbreeding. But once we move beyond the nuclear family, there can be great variation as to what kind of matings are condemned as incest. Like color vocabularies, there is cultural variation, but there is also a natural regularity that reflects our biological human nature. Evolutionary psychologists could make important contributions to our understanding of morality by following the pattern of Westermarck's biological explanation of the incest taboo to explain other areas of our moral experience. Generally, however, they have not done this, because they adhere to a rigid Kantian view of morality as expressing a transcendent "ought" that must be separated from the empirical facts of natural human desires. Larry Arnhart Department of Political Science Northern Illinois University DeKalb, Illinois 60115