Every schoolchild knows what time is. But, for every schoolchild, there is
a moment when they first encounter the paradoxes that lie just behind our
everyday understanding of time. I recall when I was a child being struck
all of a sudden by the question of whether time could end or whether it must
go on forever. It must end, for how can we conceive of the infinity of existence
stretching out before us if time is limitless? But if it ends, what happens
afterward?
I have been studying the question of what time is for much of my adult life.
But I must admit at the beginning that I am no closer to an answer now than
I was then. Indeed, even after all this study, I do not think we can answer
even the simple question: "What sort of thing is time?" Perhaps the best
thing I can say about time is to explain how the mystery has deepened for
me as I have tried to confront it. Here is another paradox about time which
I began to worry about only after growing up. We all know that clocks measure
time. But clocks are complex physical systems and hence are subject to
imperfection, breakage, and disruptions of electrical power. If I take any
two real clocks, synchronise them, and let them run, after some time, they
will always disagree about what time it is.
So which of them measures the real time? Indeed, is
there a single, absolute time which, although measured imperfectly by
any actual clock, is the true time of the world? It seems there must be,
otherwise, what do we mean when we say that some particular clock runs slow
or fast? On the other hand, what could it mean to say that something like
an absolute time exists if it can never be precisely measured?
A belief in an absolute time raises other paradoxes. Would time flow
if there were nothing in the universe? If everything stopped, if nothing
happened, would time continue?
On the other hand, perhaps there is no single absolute time. In that case,
time is only what clocks measure and, as there are many clocks and they all,
in the end, disagree, there are many times. Without an absolute time, we
can only say that time is defined relative to whichever clock we choose
to use.
This seems to be an attractive point of view, because it does not lead us
to believe in some absolute flow of time we can't
observe. But it leads to a problem, as soon as we know a little science.
One of the things physics describes is motion, and we cannot conceive
of motion without time. Thus, the notion of time is basic for physics.
Let me take the simplest law of motion, which was invented
by Galileo
and Descartes, and
formalised by Isaac Newton:
A body with no forces acting on it moves in a straight line at a constant
speed. Let's not worry here about what a straight
line is (this is the problem of space, which is perfectly analogous to
the problem of time, but which I won't discuss here). To understand what
this law is asserting, we need to know what it means to move at a constant
speed. This concept involves a notion of time, as one moves at a constant
speed when equal distances are covered in equal times.
We may then ask: With respect to which time is the motion to be constant?
Is it the time of some particular clock? If so, how do we know which clock?
We must certainly choose because, as we observed a moment ago, all real clocks
will eventually go out of synchronisation with one another. Or is it rather
that the law refers to an ideal, absolute time?
Suppose we take the point of view that the law refers to a single, absolute
time. This solves the problem of choosing which clock to use, but it raises
another problem, for no real, physical clock perfectly measures this imagined,
ideal time. How could we truly be sure whether the
statement of the law is true, if we have no access to this absolute,
ideal time? How do we tell whether some apparent speeding up or slowing down
of some body in a particular experiment is due to the failure of the law,
or only to the imperfection of the clock we are using?
Newton, when he formulated his laws of motion, chose to solve the problem
of which clock by positing the existence of an absolute time. Doing this,
he went against the judgements of his contemporaries, such as Descartes and
Gottfried Leibniz, who held that time must be only an aspect of the relationships
among real things and real processes in the world. Perhaps theirs is the
better philosophy, but as Newton knew better than anyone at the time, it
was only if one believed in an absolute time that his laws of motion, including
the one we have been discussing, make sense. Indeed,
Albert Einstein, who overthrew Newton's theory
of time, praised Newton's "courage and judgement" to go against what is clearly
the better philosophical argument, and make whatever assumptions he had to
make to invent a physics that made sense.
This debate, between time as absolute and preexisting and time as an aspect
of the relations of things, can be illustrated in the following way. Imagine
that the universe is a stage on which a string quartet or a jazz group is
about to perform. The stage and the hall are now empty, but we hear a ticking,
as someone has forgotten, after the last rehearsal, to turn off a metronome
sitting in a corner of the orchestra pit. The metronome ticking in the empty
hall is Newton's imagined absolute time, which proceeds eternally at a fixed
rate, prior to and independently of anything actually existing or happening
in the universe. The musicians enter, the universe all of a sudden is not
empty but is in motion, and they begin to weave their rhythmic art. Now,
the time that emerges in their music is not the absolute preexisting time
of the metronome; it is a relational time based on the developing real
relationships among the musical thoughts and phrases. We know this is so,
for the musicians do not listen to the metronome, they listen to one another,
and through their musical interchange, they make a time that is unique to
their place and moment in the universe.
But, all the while, in its corner the metronome ticks on, unheard by the
music makers. For Newton, the time of the musicians, the relational time,
is a shadow of the true, absolute time of the metronome. Any heard rhythm,
as well as the ticking of any real physical clock, only traces imperfectly
the true absolute time. On the other hand, for Leibniz and other philosophers,
the metronome is a fantasy that blinds us to what is really happening;
the only time is the rhythm the musicians weave together.
The debate between absolute and relational time echoes down the history of
physics and philosophy, and confronts us now, at the end of the twentieth
century, as we try to understand what notion of space and time is to replace
Newton's. If there is no absolute time, then Newton's laws of motion don't
make sense. What must replace them has to be a different kind of law that
can make sense if one measures time by any clock. That is, what is required
is a democratic rather than an autocratic law, in which any clock's time,
imperfect as it may be, is as good as any other's. Now, Leibniz was never
able to invent such a law. But Einstein did, and it is indeed one of the
great achievements of his theory of general
relativity that a way was found to express the laws of motion so that
they make sense whichever clock one uses to embody them with meaning.
Paradoxically, this is done by eliminating any reference to time from
the basic equations of the theory. The result is that time cannot
be spoken about generally or abstractly; we can only describe how the universe
changes in time if we first tell the theory exactly which real physical processes
are to be used as clocks to measure the passage of time.
So, this much being clear, why then do I say that I do not know what time
is? The problem is that general relativity is only half of the revolution
of twentieth-century physics, for there is also the
quantum theory. And quantum theory, which was originally
developed to explain the properties of atoms and molecules, took over completely
Newton's notion of an absolute ideal time.
So, in theoretical physics, we have at present not one theory of nature but
two theories: relativity and quantum mechanics, and they are based on two
different notions of time.
The key problem of theoretical physics at the present moment is to
combine general
relativity and quantum mechanics into one single theory of nature that
can finally replace the Newtonian theory overthrown at the beginning of this
century. And, indeed, the key obstacle to doing this is that the two theories
describe the world in terms of different notions of time. Unless one wants
to go backward and base this unification on the old, Newtonian notion of
time, it is clear that the problem is to bring the Leibnizian, relational
notion of time into the quantum theory. This is, unfortunately, not so easy.
The problem is that quantum mechanics allows many different, and apparently
contradictory, situations to exist simultaneously, as long as they exist
in a kind of shadow or potential reality.
(To explain this, I would have to write another essay at least as long as
this one about the quantum theory.) This applies to clocks as well, in the
same way that a cat in quantum theory can exist
in a state that is at the same time potentially living and potentially dead,
a clock can exist in a state in which it is simultaneously running the
usual way and running backward. So, if there were a quantum theory of
time, it would have to deal not only with freedom to choose different physical
clocks to measure time, but with the simultaneous existence, at least
potentially, of many different clocks. The first, we have learned from Einstein
how to do; the second has, so far, been too much for our imaginations.
So the problem of what time is remains unsolved. But it is worse than this,
because relativity theory seems to require other changes in the notion of
time. One of them concerns my opening question, whether time can begin or
end, or whether it flows eternally. For relativity is a theory in which time
can truly start and stop.
One circumstance in which this happens is inside of a black hole.
A black hole is the result of the collapse of a massive star, when it has
burned all its nuclear fuel and thus ceased to burn as a star. Once it is
no longer generating heat, nothing can halt the collapse of a sufficiently
massive star under the force of its own gravity. This process feeds on itself,
because the smaller the star becomes, the stronger the force by which its
parts are mutually attracted to one another. One consequence of this is that
a point is reached at which something would have to go faster than light
to escape from the surface of the star. Since nothing can travel faster than
light, nothing can leave. This is why we call it a black hole, for not even
light can escape from it.
However, let us think not of this, but of what happens to the star itself.
Once it becomes invisible to us, it takes only a short time for the whole
star to be compressed to the point at which it has an infinite density of
matter and an infinite gravitational field. The problem is, what happens
then? The problem, indeed, is what, in such a circumstance, "then" might
mean. If time is only given meaning by the motion of physical clocks, then
we must say that time stops inside of each black hole. Because once
the star reaches the state of infinite density and infinite gravitational
field, no further change can take place, and no physical process can go on
that would give meaning to time. Thus, the theory simply asserts that time
stops.
The problem is in fact even worst than this, because general relativity allows
for the whole universe to collapse like a black hole, in which case, time
stops everywhere. It can also allow for time to begin. This is the
way we understand the big bang, the most popular
theory, currently, of the origin of the universe.
Perhaps the central problem that those of us who are trying to combine relativity
and quantum mechanics think about is what is really happening inside a black
hole. If time really stops there, then we must contemplate that all time,
everywhere, comes to a stop in the collapse of the universe. On the other
hand, if it does not stop, then we must contemplate a whole, limitless world
inside each black hole, forever beyond our vision. Moreover, this is not
just a theoretical problem, because a black hole is formed each time a massive
enough star comes to the end of its life and collapses, and this mystery
is occurring, somewhere in the vast universe we can see, perhaps one hundred
times a second.
So, what is time? Is it the greatest mystery? No, the greatest mystery must
be that each of us is here, for some brief time, and that part of the
participation that the universe allows us in its larger existence is to ask
such questions. And to pass on, from schoolchild to schoolchild, the joy
of wondering, of asking, and of telling each other what we know and what
we don't know.
LEE SMOLIN, a theoretical physicist,
is professor of physics and member of the Center for Gravitational Physics
and Geometry at Pennsylvania State University. Together with Abhay Ashtekar
and Roger Penrose, he holds
a five-year National Science Foundation grant which supports their work in
quantum gravity.
In addition to being considered one of the premier scientists working in
the field of quantum gravity, he has also made contributions to cosmology,
particle physics, and the foundations of quantum mechanics. Smolin is perhaps
best known for a new approach to the quantization of general relativity,
and as such, he has been identified as a leader of one of the most promising
new directions currently being pursued in science. He has also been working
on a proposal for applying evolutionary theory to cosmology, which
has received a great deal of press, including articles in The
Independent, New
Scientist, and Physics World as well as two programs on BBC
World Service. He is the author of more than fifty scientific papers and
several articles for general audiences, and is at work on a popular book
about quantum gravity.
Further Reading
How Things Are: A Science Toolkit for the Mind
[RI Lectures
1999 Arrows of time Neil Johnson video JB12] |
Chaos | Quantum | Logic | Cosmos | Conscious | Belief | Elect. | Art | Chem. | Maths |